Tumgik
#Graham Harman
chaosloon · 2 years
Quote
Graham Harman’s universe is a universe populated by circuses and clowns, vampires, unnamed monsters, fire and cotton, and a host of other frightening and delightful carnivalesque entities that erupt across his pages like so many apparitions that simultaneously withdraw and capture us with their inherent fascination and allure.
Levi R. Bryant in The Democracy of Objects (2011), referring primarily to Graham Harman’s Circus Philosophicus (2010).
8 notes · View notes
Text
Notes on Metaphysics
Notes on Metaphysics
Where does one Start? Let us consider the following idea by Dewey, quoted fully below, as one of the guidelines to think about where to start metaphysics:  “It is not strange then that philosophies which have been at odds on every other point have been one in the conviction that the ultimately real is fixed and unchanging, even though they have been as far apart as the poles in their ideas of…
View On WordPress
2 notes · View notes
aioleis · 18 days
Text
————
In the book Object-Oriented Ontology by Graham Harman, alongside his explaniation to the core of that phylosophy, openly thesing and mocking the String theory, which assupt as best game in town.
A candide for to be theory of everything, but still lack of so many things, like the exaptence the forces of sensual objects. 
Nearly the entire planet spent its days in the tedium of thinking itself a part of a mere menagerie, bound to live within the perfect celestial omens drawn out for them by the godfathers, in a monotheistic universe, until Galileo made statements that confused everyone's minds.
We are still searching for that theory of everything. Searching for the mystery of connection, from the day we arrived, through ancient mythologies to today's daily horoscopes.
Brief look at our vision on universal logic, historic of the space, four false assuption of the super-string theory from (OOO) ;
(revised, for orginal pdf)
In recent decades, few intellectual topics have captured the public imagination like the search for a so-called ‘theory of everything’ in physics. 
Brian Greene of Columbia University, who views the currently popular ‘string theory’ as the best existing candidate for a theory explaining the composition of matter and the structure of the cosmos.
The search for unifications in physics has already given humanity some of its most heroic moments.
In the early 1600s, Galileo established the falsity of the ancient view that there is one kind of physics for the eternal bodies in the sky and a completely different kind for the corrupt and decaying things down here on the earth; instead, he showed that one physics governs every portion of the universe.
One of the first and most illustrious examples of the prophetic power of science is reported by Galileo Galilei in his Sidereus Nuncius: 
I feel sure that the surface of the Moon is not perfectly smooth, free from inequalities and exactly spherical, as a large school of philosophers considers with regard to the Moon and the other heavenly bodies, but that, on the contrary, it is full of inequalities, uneven, full of hollows and protuberances, just like the surface of the earth itself, which is varied everywhere by lofty mountains and deep valleys.4 
At the time this was written, the dominant Aristotelian doctrine taught that the cosmos, along with all the elements that composed it, was perfectly spherical, and that no imperfection was allowed to exist outside of the earth.
Gazing through his telescope, Galileo was struck by a blasphemous revelation: that the moon, and by extension the entire universe, was irremediably dirty and subject to the same processes of degradation and dissolution that we experience in our world.
The apparently innocuous words of his statement, supported by the reasonable argument of scientific observation, hide an actual, gruesome deicide; if the universe is not perfect and eternal, how could God be?
As we now know, the moon’s surface was disfigured by asteroids—celestial omens of death whose distorted, eccentric trajectories escape the comprehension of spherical cosmology.
Interestingly, Galileo somehow expiated his blasphemy by opening the way to the formulation of the principle of the conservation of energy—the first principle of thermodynamics—through his experiments on motion.
The spherical nature of the universe was somehow preserved in the symmetry of the laws of mechanical motion, which imply the total reversibility of all dynamic processes and thus the nonexistence of time as a material drive toward degradation.
This paved the way for the even more fateful unification announced in Sir Isaac Newton’s Principia in 1687. In this masterpiece of the history of science, Newton demonstrated that the movement of celestial bodies and the falling of objects to the ground are governed by one and the same force: gravity, as everyone calls it today. 
In the 1860s, James Clerk Maxwell was unify the previously separate forces of electricity and magnetism, and established further that light and electromagnetism travel at the same speed, strongly suggesting that light is simply another manifestation of the same force.
From this consideration it obviously follows that the ultimate prophecy of doom channelled by science is the second principle of thermodynamics in its statistical-mechanical interpretation, as understood by Ludwig Boltzmann: 
After this confession you will take it with more tolerance if I am so bold as to claim your attention for a quite trifling and narrowly circumscribed question. 
[...] The second law proclaims a steady degradation of energy until all tensions that might still perform work and all visible motions in the universe would have to cease. All attempts at saving the universe from this thermal death have been unsuccessful, and to avoid raising hopes I cannot fulfil, let me say at once that I too shall here refrain from making such attempts. (5) 
The ‘narrowly circumscribed question’ of condemning the entire cosmos to irremediable heat death breaks with any surviving hope that the universe may be, in any capacity, spherical, reversible, or eternal.
Boltzmann was a meticulous scientist and a convinced upholder of the inherent boundaries of science and human knowledge; but despite his understandable caution in approaching the subject of his own ground-breaking discoveries, the proof of his H-theorem, containing a probabilistic argument in support of the second principle of thermodynamics, is not merely a speculation on the behaviour of an ideal gas of non-interacting particles, but rather the elaborate conjuration of an eldritch aberration.
As we diligently follow the intricate steps of this twisted ritual, summoning functions and variables and transmuting them through the arcane operations of calculus, we finally reach the Quod Erat Demonstrandum, manifesting the apocalyptic truth of the death of the universe and unleashing it into reality. There is minimal need of scientific understanding to operate the conjuring machine of thermodynamics; it just works—until it works no more. 
-
By the 1970s four forces of nature had been recognized: gravity, electromagnetism, the strong nuclear force (which holds atoms together) and the weak nuclear force (which governs radioactive decay).
The 1979 Nobel Prize in Physics went jointly to the physicists Sheldon Lee Glashow, Abdus Salam and Steven Weinberg for their unified theory of the ‘electroweak’ force, while the strong force was accounted for at roughly the same time by QCD, or quantum chromodynamics.
By the mid-1970s, physics had its Standard Model of Particle Physics, which was more or less completed in 2012 by the apparent discovery of the Higgs boson at CERN in Geneva. 
In the early twentieth century, quantum theory unified various phenomena of heat, light and atomic motion by explaining them as occurring through discrete jumps rather than continuous increase or decrease. 
Among the remaining problems with the Standard Model is that it does not unify gravity with the electromagnetic, strong and weak forces. The pursuit of a workable theory of ‘quantum gravity’ continues to this day, and along with the discovery by astronomers of the still inexplicable dark matter and dark energy, the search for quantum gravity is one of the most likely triggers of the next revolution in physics. 
***
After Graham wrote those, little note about the discovery of black star.
NEMESIS or THE BLACK SUN
Because You love cremation grounds I have made my heart one so that You Black Goddess of the Burning Grounds can always dance there. 
No desires are left, Mā, on the pyre for the fire burns in my heart, and I have covered everything with its ash to prepare for Your coming.
via: R.F. McDermott, Singing to the Goddess: Poems to Kālī and Umā from Bengal (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 74–75.
***
Nonetheless, no matter how carefully science insists on tracing the limits of its own understanding, barricading itself behind walls of axioms and boundary conditions, it inevitably becomes an oracle, a spiritual medium, opening a laceration onto a radical Outside and summoning an invasion of voices of long-lost demons into our world, not unlike a cursed Cassandra who refuses to surrender to her own prophetic utterances. 
The topic of unified theories is so exciting that physicists have created a small industry of readable popular books on the theme, with Greene’s The Elegant Universe one of the most prominent among them.
Maybe we shoulld agree on Graham’s phases:
I certainly agree with Greene that ‘we should not rest until we have a theory whose range of applicability is limitless’. My point of disagreement will sound surprising in the current intellectual climate: I do not agree that physics, or even natural science more generally, is the right place to find such a unified theory. In my view, the ‘theory whose range of applicability is limitless’ can only be found in philosophy, and especially in the type of philosophy called Object-Oriented Ontology (OOO).
Though the rapid advance of modern physics has been one of the most reassuring chapters of human history, I see it as a field that excludes far too much to give us a theory of everything.
Assumptions that graham found wrong in String Theory.
Claim that physics (and string theory in particular) has limitless applicability. 
String theory is not the only candidate for a ‘theory of everything’, but it remains the most popular, and for many the most promising.
The theory has been around in some form since the 1960s, but became an especially hot topic two decades later. 
String theory postulates that matter is composed of vibrating one-dimensional strings twisting through ten dimensions, rather than the four dimensions of space–time that Einsteinian physics accepts. In so-called ‘ M-theory’, Edward Witten’s 1995 modification of the string landscape, the total number of dimensions was expanded to eleven. 
Numerous beautiful mathematical and physical results can be derived from the theory, including a possible account of the everelusive quantum gravity, meaning a theory of gravity that can be explained in terms of quantum mechanics just as the electromagnetic, strong and weak forces already have been.
Nonetheless, a backlash against string theory began in the twenty-first century, as can be seen in the widely read critical books by physicists Lee Smolin and Richard Woit.
Perhaps the most frequent accusation against string theory by sceptics is that it cannot be experimentally tested, and is therefore said to be little more than a mathematical exercise of no direct relevance to physics.
Another problem is that so many thousands of different string theories are mathematically possible that there is no reason to choose one in particular, except on the shaky basis that we must obviously choose the theory that fits the structure of the universe we know: for otherwise we would not be here today to have debates about it. 
This line of reasoning is known as the ‘anthropic principle’, viewed by many scientists with contempt but by others as a pivotal intellectual tool. Lastly, Smolin in particular is alarmed by the near-monopoly of string theory in the leading graduate courses in physics, which for him means that the entire profession has put all its eggs in a single, experimentally baseless basket. 
String theory would have become textbook science, learned by students everywhere as a basic fact about our world, much like Einstein’s theory of gravity or the periodic table of chemical elements. My claim is that even under this optimal scenario of maximum scientific triumph, string theory would still not be a ‘theory of everything’. To see why, let’s examine what I take to be the four false assumptions behind statements that string theory’s range of applicability is limitless. 
First False Assumption: everything that exists must be physical. 
A successful string theory would sum up everything we know about the structure and behaviour of physical matter. But this makes it a ‘theory of everything’ only on the condi- tion that everything is physical.
Of course, many people do not see it this way.
Religion is a far weaker force in Europe than it used to be, though it remains significantly stronger in the United States, and very much stronger in other parts of the world. Among adherents of all religions, belief in immaterial gods and souls is nearly universal. Many other people around the world, including a number of unreligious ones, still believe in ghosts and spirits. In almost every country, a number of buildings stand out for their reputation as being especially haunted.
In more refined circles we find Jungian psychology, which affirms the existence of unconscious and immaterial archetypes shared collectively by all human beings.
By hypothesis, a mainstream physicist will dismiss all such ideas as unscientific rubbish; A ‘theory of everything’, does not mean a theory that includes all of the nonsense that gullible people think is real, but only a theory of what rational and scientifically minded people know to be real: the physical–material universe. (?)
Though I for one am not particularly convinced by Jungian psychology, I do read Jung from time to time and find that he improves my imagination.
And I would certainly hate to live in a world where Jungian societies were liquidated by the Rationality Police or demoralized by general public mockery.
But let’s suppose we agree with the scepticism of anti-spirutual stories, and join the crowd that disbelief about any gods, souls, ghosts, spirits, unconscious archetypes or other supposed non-material entities. Even if we were to walk this far down in that the path, and even under the supposition that string theory were confirmed by rock-solid evidence, 
I would still not agree with her that this meritorious theory could count as a ‘theory of everything’. For we can think of plenty of things that are not physical but which are almost certainly real.
For one thing, material objects always exist somewhere, but in the case of the VOC it is not at all clear where that place of existence would be. 
The Dutch East India Company (VOC) challenges the notion of being a material object, as material objects have a specific location, which the VOC lacked. The VOC wasn't confined to its Amsterdam headquarters, as its operations were primarily in Southeast Asia, governed independently by a Governor-General without needing to consult Dutch shareholders. Also, its Asian capital, Batavia (now Jakarta), housed only a fraction of its resources and employees. The VOC's regulations applied across its territories, further complicating its physical location. Moreover, the VOC existed from 1602 to 1795, outliving any individual or ship associated with it, thus defying the characteristics of a material thing like a quark, electron, or vibrating string.
There is an old philosophical paradox known as the Ship of Theseus, which poses the problem of whether the ship remains the same even when we gradually or suddenly replace each of its boards with a new one – especially if we assemble the old boards together nearby as a rival vessel to the new ship. Without going further into this paradox I wish to emphasize what I take to be a chief lesson of the VOC case study:
the irreducibility of larger objects to the sum total of their material compo- nents. The Dutch East India Company was not just a collec- tion of atoms and strings at various locations in space–time, but to a large extent was able to survive the motion and dis- appearance of these tiny elements while making use of others. 
Second False Assumption: everything that exists must be basic and simple.
Are we missing the point ? we have missed the point.
For while it may be true that the VOC or the Ship of Theseus can survive despite the turnover of their material pieces, they certainly cannot exist without any material pieces at all. If over time the VOC only lost atoms and never gained any, there would finally come a point where its various ships, cargoes and officers would crumble to dust and the VOC would cease to exist.
Maybe theory never meant to tell us there cannot be higher-order objects that seem to endure despite massive turnover in their material components. But such objects must always be made of some physical matter, even if it is relatively unimportant whether one hydrogen atom or another happens to be found in the brain of the VOC’s Governor-General.
The fallacy that the philosopher Sam Coleman has termed ‘smallism’, as if the real ele- ments in any situation were the tiniest components to which everything can be broken down.5 The mid-and large-sized objects that surround us (from cups, tables and flowers to skyscrapers and elephants) seem to have independent fea- tures of their own, but according to thheory these larger objects ultimately receive all of their properties from those of their components; after all, without these small components the larger objects could never exist.
What this argument misses is the phenomenon known as emergence, in which new properties appear when smaller objects are joined together into a new one.6 This is visible everywhere in human life. For example, a high-school friend and I noticed one summer that girls would often walk together in groups of three, but that boys were almost always found alone or in pairs. We wondered why this was so, until my friend rather cryptically nailed it by saying that ‘three boys together are already a gang’. I believe his meaning was as follows: there is something vaguely menacing in the air as soon as three young males come together, and hence this practice is subtly discouraged under normal situations, which do not provide a welcome setting for menace. If the observation is correct, then three boys together have as a vague emergent property ‘gang-like threat to society’ that is found neither in two boys nor in three girls. 
This is also true in the sciences, as can be seen with especial ease in a field such as organic chemistry: all organic compounds contain carbon, but there are millions of organic compounds, each with its own unique features.
Sometimes the defenders of emergence push their luck and make unnecessary additional claims, asserting for instance that the features of organic compounds ‘could not have been predicted’ from the features of carbon.
But quantum chemistry does allow us to predict the properties of larger molecules before they are actually created. And predictability is not even the point, since even if we could predict the features of all larger entities from their ultimate physical constituents, the ability to predict would not change the fact that the larger entity actually possesses emergent qualities not found in its components.
This is equally clear in human life. Perhaps a couple is about to be married, and all of their friends see clearly in advance that the marriage will be disas- trous. Now, let’s imagine that the friends of the couple are completely right: not only does the marriage fail, but it fails in precisely those ways and on the exact timetable that the friends had predicted. But notice that the predictability of this marital failure does not entail that the marriage is nothing more than the sum total of the two pre-existing indi- viduals who were married. In other words, the emergent real- ity of an object composed jointly of multiple parts (such as a married couple) does not hinge on the predictability or unpredictability of how it ultimately turns out. Emergence does not require mysterious results, but only that the mar- ried couple has joint features not found in either of the indi- viduals in isolation. The same would hold true if the friends were completely wrong and the marriage led to eternal and blissful harmony: the point is that the existence of the mar- riage as an emergent object over and above the two individ- ual partners has nothing to do with whether its success or failure could be foreseen. 
Another prejudice infects portions of the history of phil- osophy in the view that only that which is natural truly exists. This doctrine is especially prominent in the philoso- phy of the German polymath G. W. Leibniz (1646–1716), who distinguishes sharply between what he calls ‘substances’ and ‘aggregates’. Substances are simple, soul-like entities (known as ‘monads’), all of them created by God at the beginning of time.7 By contrast, aggregates are compounds such as machines, circles of men holding hands, or pairs of diamonds glued together. For Leibniz such aggregates are merely laugh- able stand-ins for true substances, which can exist only by nature rather than artifice. OOO rejects this view given that machines, much like the Dutch East India Company (another example mocked by Leibniz), can be treated as unified objects no less than an atom or tiny vibrating string. In short, naturalness is no better as a criterion of objecthood than smallness or simplicity. As for the true criteria for what qualifies as an object, we will discuss them at the end of this chapter. 
Third False Assumption:
everything that exists must be real.
One of the greatest fictional heroes of all time is surely the detective Sherlock Holmes, in the stories of Sir Arthur Conan Doyle. In writing these stories, Doyle tried to house his detective at a fictitious address on a real London street: namely, 221B Baker Street. Yet the very real London thoroughfare called Baker Street was later extended to go as far as the 200s, thereby putting the fictional flat of Holmes and Dr. Watson within the range of real-life city addresses. It is said that some of the Sherlock Holmes fans who visit the currently accepted address, now home to a gift shop and museum, labour under the misconception that the detective was a real historical person.
The retelling of this story usually provokes cruel laughter at the expense of these naive tourists. Yet there is a charming grain of truth in their ignorance: the fact that the detective is such a beloved and memorable character that one can easily imagine him resting comfortably at home on Baker Street, and picture him in a number of situations that did not actually occur in Doyle’s works (as in the current television series in which Holmes, played by Benedict Cumberbatch, solves cases in present-day London).
This brings us to a third objection to the global ambitions of string theory. Namely, a successful string theory would not be able to tell us anything about Sherlock Holmes, and this alone suffices to disqualify it as a ‘theory of everything’. For Holmes is a fictional personage, and thus was never composed of strings or of any other physical material. 
Nor is it even necessary to invoke celebrity fictional characters such as those who inhabit novels and films, since we are surrounded at all times by fictions.
For example, any real orange or lemon, as I perceive it, is a vast oversimplification of the real citrus-objects in the world that are submitted to rough translation by the human senses and human brain.
The real orange or lemon is no more accessible to my human perception than it is to a mosquito or dog, whose organs translate the fruits differently into their own types of experience. In this respect, all of the objects we experience are merely fictions: simplified models of the far more complex objects that continue to exist when I turn my head away from them, not to mention when I sleep or die.
A successful string theory, like any fundamental theory of physics, is aimed entirely at the discovery of real physical entities rather than fictitious ones. And while it is already hard to imagine a basic physical theory adequately addressing any emergent mid- or large-sized entity (let us use ‘entity’ as another synonym for ‘object’ and ‘thing’), it is even harder to imagine a successful string theory teaching us anything about the fictional objects of literature and everyday perception, a field where natural science normally does not tread.
This is no small matter, since fictions are an integral part of human experience, and of animal life more generally.
Along with the examples already given, recall that we humans spend much of our time worrying about things that can never happen or simply never do. We are frequently deluded about our own capacities, whether under, or overestimating them.
We spend a large portion of our lives in nocturnal dreams, and despite recent criticism of psychoanalysis, it is doubtful that these dreams can be understood in purely chemical or neurological terms.
All of this is to say nothing of our entertainment media, which often feature dragons, rings of invisibility, aliens assaulting the earth, or the intimate lives of characters who exist for two hours on a screen before vanishing from the cosmos forever.
For many of us, artists such as Beethoven and Picasso are as worthy of esteem as Newton and Einstein, though the latter discuss such undeniable realities as light and moons while the former create pure fictions.
Any ‘theory of everything’ that dismisses the reality of fictions, or passes them over in silence, is by that fact alone unable to reach its goal of covering everything. 
Fourth False Assumption:
everything that exists must be able to be stated accurately in literal propositional language.
Here are some scientific statements, chosen at random from the three books of science nearest to hand in my living room: 
1. ‘Some hydrogen atoms can escape the Earth’s gravity and are lost to space, [while] some meteoritic material comes in (about forty-four tons per day on average) . . .’ (8)
2. ‘As Schrödinger pointed out, if M represents a cat and R takes two possible values . . . and the decay event triggers a device that kills the cat, then the cat will be neither alive nor dead after the measurement interaction, according to the orthodox interpretation.’9 
3. ‘All other interventions, such as, for example, cold, heat, acids, alkalis, electrical currents, [the bell] responds to as any other piece of metal would. But we know . . . that 
a muscle behaves in a completely different way. It responds to all external interventions in the same way: by contracting.’10 
These are admirably formed statements conveying information that we hope to be true, though every scientist knows that many apparently rock-solid statements are later aban- doned or modified in the face of new evidence. Moreover, it is not just science that makes such statements.
History does the same. I need only turn elsewhere on my living room bookshelf:
‘But Mo-ch’o was growing old, and the Turks began to weary of his cruelty and tyranny. Many chiefs offered their allegiance to China, and the Bayirku of the upper Kerulen revolted.’11 
Or simply this: ‘At this time, too, Venice had become the intellectual centre of Italy.’ (12)
All of these statements can be understood clearly by anyone with a basic secondary education. And of course we make statements of this sort constantly even in non-scholarly contexts.
It is easy to state as follows:
‘Leicester City stunned the sports world in 2016 by finishing on top of the English Premier League.’ Or I can look at the text messages on my phone and see that my wife, a university food scientist, needs me to pick up some items for her class on sensory analysis: ‘Here are the items I need before 11 o’clock. 1 pack of original Oreo cookies. 2 litres of drinking water. 1 carton of Florida Natural Original Orange Juice, with pulp.’
All these examples are literal statements that convey information directly. And thus it is easy to assume that nothing can be real unless we are able to refer to it in an accurate prose statement that conveys literal properties of the thing in question.
Apparently, the only alternative would be fuzzy metaphors or merely negative statements that teach us nothing. 
The American philosopher Daniel Dennett is very much a literalist in this sense.
I am both amused and appalled by his mockery of wine-tasting in the following passage: 
Could Gallo Brothers replace their human wine-tasters with a machine? . . . Pour the sample in the funnel and, in a few minutes or hours, the system would type out a chemical assay, along with commentary: ‘a flamboyant and velvety Pinot, though lacking in stamina’ – or words to such effect . . . [B]ut surely [note Dennett’s sarcasm] no matter how ‘sensitive’ or ‘discriminating’ such a system becomes, it will never have, and enjoy, what we do when we taste a wine: the qualia of conscious experience . . . If you share that intuition, you believe that there are qualia in the sense that I am targeting for demolition. (13)
To summarize, Dennett thinks that the wine is literally and adequately expressed by its ‘chemical assay’, though his imagined machine will also add sarcastic poetic commentary at the expense of human readers who disagree with his views. Nonetheless, he holds, there is no special conscious human experience of wine that would require the elusive figurative description of a flamboyant and velvety Pinot.
OOO holds that Dennett is wrong about this, and not just in the obvious sense that the taste of wine for humans resists any precise literal description. Instead, the claim of OOO is that literal language is always an oversimplification, since it describes things in terms of definite literal properties even though objects are never just bundles of literal properties (despite Hume’s view to the contrary).
It is not just that the chemical assay of the wine fails to do justice to the human experience of tasting wine, but that it fails to do justice even to the chemical–physical structure of the wine. This may sound like a startling claim, since the natural sciences are generally regarded as the court of final appeal in our era, just as the Church was in the medieval period.
But I will develop this anti-literalist claim throughout the present book. In so doing, I will build on the philosophical work of Heidegger, who also gives priority to poetic over literal language – though admit- tedly in ways that sometimes verge on Black Forest peasant kitsch, and though his statements against science are often needlessly extreme. 14 
Thus I will make the case differently from how Heidegger did, though I agree with his basic line of reasoning: the reality of things is always withdrawn or veiled rather than directly accessible, and therefore any attempt to grasp that reality by direct and literal language will inevitably misfire.
In a sense, this point by Heidegger merely develops Aristotle’s ancient claim in his Metaphysics that individual things cannot be defined, since things are always concrete while definitions are made of universals. (15)
0 notes
trusswork · 11 months
Text
various
Fuller's morality of duty : morality of aspiration :: fear of Hell : love of Heaven
~
Nothing is more human, and animal, than to want to express your feelings, and to have other people recognize, acknowledge, sympathize with these.
The people to be wary of are those who at the small moments want to see themselves, and want others to see them, having those emotions. With the Twitter user who routinely and lavishly displays his outrage and adoration, and the zine artist who visually dramatizes (rather than expresses) her moment-to-moment autobiographical feelings without any remove from herself, there is some reality and responsivity lost.
~
Graham Harman's Guerilla Metaphysics: Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things = why is it more than interesting commentary on aspects of Aristotle + Heidegger. As good as his writing sometimes is in some ways, it is not a revelation.
0 notes
anaxerneas · 1 year
Text
By placing any independent natural world outside of philosophy, Husserl pays a terrible price; his bracketing of the natural world is a brutally idealist gesture. In vain do his disciples protest that consciousness is never an isolated entity but alwavs already outside itself through its intentional acts of observing, judging, hating, and loving. For in phenomenology these objects have no autonomy from consciousness. Their existence is already threatened if I shift my attention, fall asleep, or die, and all the more so if all rational beings in the universe were exterminated. A Husserlian might respond to these scenarios by claiming that the essence of these objects would endure even after the death of all thinking creatures. But even this response would miss the point: the things would still have no autonomous reality apart from being the objects of actual or potential observation. They are granted no secret life or inherent causal power, but are "real" only insofar as they might now or someday appear to consciousness. But unless objects are granted reality apart from such appearance, it is pointless to say that humans are always already engaged with things rather than being isolated minds, or that they are passive participants in an event rather than active constitutors of the world. Husserl's intentional realm has nothing real about it, nothing autonomous from an observer.
Graham Harman, The Quadruple Object
0 notes
forensicated · 5 months
Text
Wishing you all a very Merry Christmas, hope you have a wonderful time whatever you end up doing, however you end up spending it.
3 notes · View notes
vapourchild · 2 months
Text
thinking about things and stuff (literally)
am currently typing half asleep and thinking about the desolation of things; not just material things, but intangible objects like defunct ideologies or etiolated ideals, or the alien fossils of dead civilisations and their practices. objects in a see and perceive their contexts. objects enter into relations with one another just as we enter into relations with objects; objects are affected and affect just as much as subjects do. and so objects have a kind of deep, taciturn knowledge that they keep hidden behind their wordless bare being. a hidden knowing, slightly melancholic.
i own a starbucks tumbler that was bought the year i was born. the thing that struck me about it was its innocence. it does not know about the 2008 financial crisis. it has, as it seems to me, a perpetual air of naivety and hope about it. because of its objective stasis (it is not alive or subjectively conscious), it is a perpetual material precipitate of its zeitgeist. it knows things, it sees things, it holds things, it holds time, within itself, like a fly in amber, or like a rarefied essence.
or think of the virtual decrepitude of an old 2000s game; for me, it’s virtual families 2, a sims ripoff with 2000s graphics and a suburban american home which is mysteriously ruined and you have to renovate it to unlock new spaces for generations of your virtual family to live in. one day i lost interest in the game and abandoned it, never to open the app again. i wonder what that space is like now, those immaterial rooms, with their dark wooden floors and the lazily drifting specks of white pixel dust. the old yellowing sofa, and the stained blue and pink beds for the children. all these things, these places; i wonder what they know, what they see, what spirit they hold inside of them. (something something phenomenology of space—i havent read that book yet, sorry)
i don’t think we (i) give enough credit to the idea of objective interactions outside of the subject, for the almost mystical interest it offers. the mysticism of the thing in itself, infinitely other to our experience, with its knowledge withdrawn from us. the ultimate esoteric knowledge. or what about things interacting with other things, with no supervention from the subject? like a fire burning cotton, or a storm felling a tree. objects themselves are inaccessible to each other in themselves. everything is only ever in brief contact with everything else in a specific, limited way. and so the world is shrouded in deep mystery, endarkened, nubilated. the mystique of a pre-enlightenment world returns, with its strangeness and sublime vastness.
0 notes
cliozaur · 20 days
Text
Tumblr media
It’s amusing that Philip Quast played so many gay characters throughout his career:
Patroclus (Paris); Achilles (Troilus and Cressida); Grahame Chandler (Fix); Georges (La Cage aux Folles); Richard Bowden (Me and Mrs Jones)
As well as a couple of probably asexual ones: Father Pearse J. Harman (Ultraviolet); Javert (Les Misérables)
Let me know if I missed something.
18 notes · View notes
lizbethborden · 8 months
Text
Tag 9 people you'd like to get to know better tagged by @beatifiq and @sillybush :)
Last Song: "Red Wine Supernova" by Chappell Roan--I'm trying to listen to her album a lot and get all the songs down before I see her :) I am also listening to a podcast called "History of Philosophy Without Any Gaps" which I'm really enjoying. I'm on Anaxagoras rn.
Favorite color: Red :)
Currently watching: I'm in a perpetual state of rewatching. 30 Rock, Bojack Horseman, Futurama mostly.
Last movie: No clue. Probably a horror movie? It might have been Carrie 2002 with Patricia Clarkson #notimmune
Currently reading: A few things! Papyrus by Irene Vallejo, Weird Realism: Lovecraft and Philosophy by Graham Harman, Beloved by Toni Morrison, ummm. Probably others.
Sweet/spicy/savory: Savory :)
Relation status: Single.
Current obsession(s): Hmmm... Not sure. I have certain specific areas of interest that I tend to return to.
Last thing I Googled: "Havahart trap" (I have a mouse problem rn)
Currently working on: Decompressing. This is the "Sunday" of my weekend, so I'm trying to get in a good chill headspace. I'm having a Brooklyn Cider House cider called "Raw" that tastes just like a dry white wine, which is fun. The beastie creature is playing with his toys (an empty seltzer can) (I can spend like $60 on toys and he'll still just want to play with empty seltzer cans and bottles) rn.
Not going to tag anyone because I'm #shy but feel free to do this. :)
5 notes · View notes
transmutationisms · 1 year
Note
Hey Caden! I hope you are well!!! I’ve been reading Donna Haraway for my thesis for a Science Fiction course on ethnofuturism and I was wondering if you’ve ever read her stuff or if there was anything to correlate between Succession and her work since her comments on biomedical literature, nature, and artufactualism remind me both of what you’ve written and a lot of what Succession has said on the body and the manipulations of what is fact and fiction. I’m just curious so sorry for the weirdly worded ask and no pressure if it’s not a subject with a lot to comment on!
hi megan! i'm good ^_^ hope you're also well!
my familiarity with haraway is partially secondhand (ie, she pops up in a lot of people's footnotes, so i'm more likely to encounter her ideas that way than by reading her directly) but yes, i do think there are connections to be made here.
haraway works in a social constructivist paradigm (stop me if you've heard this before) that emphasises the socially embedded ('artifactual') nature of scientific theory and the artificiality of the boundaries between nature and culture, nature and technology, and technology and the body. my very strong opinion is that succession makes a lot of overlapping claims, such as by showing the socially constructed nature of truth (the roys constantly narrativise and re-narrativise, and the show rarely plays god by telling us who's 'correct'), and in the way the characters use language (the words are often empty, meaningless, or semantically re-deployed, thus challenging accepted categories of fact and methods of fact-making).
in this vein, i've written a little before about succession as post-structuralist. the major difference i would identify between haraway and succ (besides specific subject matter) is that haraway works in science and technology studies, a field with a predominantly sociological slant, whereas i think succ makes its critique more through the tools of historicisation. however, these methods obviously have a tendency to bleed into one another, and there's a reason most historians of the past few generations have a broadly constructivist philosophical orientation.
if you're into this stuff you might like some of the other sts/philsci classics (bruno latour, david bloor, paul feyerabend, sandra harding, simon schaffer) or the standard post-structuralists (deleuze, derrida, foucault, etc) or even some of the new materialists (jane bennett, karen barad, graham harman, quentin meillassoux). truly very sexy stuff i'm always reading succ through my little constructivist-historicist-materialist lens >:)
11 notes · View notes
chaosloon · 2 years
Quote
God is dead. And, as a matter of fact, I don’t feel too well either.
Alenka Zupančič, quoted by Graham Harman in Architecture and Objects: Art After Nature (2022)
5 notes · View notes
Text
METAPHYSICS / ONTOLOGY 
(NOTE: posting another part of my ongoing dissertation. This is part of an unedited and working chapter, there are gaps and this text at the moment, which I am editing as I am posting this.) Since this study raises the question of the ontological models behind the architectural theories of style, it is important that I explicate what is ontology, and also what is object-oriented ontology or OOO,…
View On WordPress
0 notes
baeddel · 2 years
Text
btw, Graham Harman has me blocked on twitter. he seems to block anybody who interacts with his posts who he doesn’t know personally. and as we said he deleted his wordpress, upon which he immediately made a new wordpress, and several posts from his first month using the new wordpress address site traffic. he’s one of the first philosopher-bloggers, yet is also tormented by it, constantly restaging the play only to straightway draw the curtains.
20 notes · View notes
perkwunos · 2 years
Text
There is a common mischaracterization of Whitehead among more “continental” contemporary spaces, evidenced in Graham Harman’s critique of him for “overmining”, ie having subjects be entirely determined by their relations, understanding a “prehension” (which is then the constituent of actual entities) to be relations—which is technically ignorant of Whitehead’s mature system, in which a prehension refers to the internal determinations of actual entities understood at their most concrete level, which is as acts of feeling; these feelings can then be in relation to other actualities (ie, a feeling of a feeling: physical prehension) or an independent activity (a feeling of a specific quality or tone in itself abstracted from the physical environment: conceptual prehension). Now I wonder if this mischaracterization is in part an effect of Whitehead often being introduced in these environments via Deleuze, who stated “every prehension is already a prehension of another prehension, either to capture it or to exclude it: the prehension is by nature open, open to the world.” I say this not so much to blame Deleuze—who was only really bringing up Whitehead in a cursory way in a wider study of the history of philosophy—but just thinking about the ways philosophies get filtered over time, coming to us already interpreted by others. Now, the flip side to this is that Whitehead himself can say some things that contribute to this confusion about prehensions as purely relational—especially if you focus on his earlier rather than later works, I think.
10 notes · View notes
onetwofeb · 2 years
Text
The ‘thingliness’ of the pandemic is shown by pointing to the canonic story about Thales of Miletus: “When Thales of Miletus fell down the well while lost in thought, it was because he didn’t stop to contemplate the well’s agential ‘thingliness’ first.” This sentence is applied to our global dealings with the pandemic. In a critique of the pandemic philosophy the intricate relationship between capitalist realism and idealism is inspected, as exemplified in the dispute between Graham Harman and Alain Badiou. The theoretical fetishism that underlies object-oriented and other shallow ontologies are then addressed. In conclusion it is found that in order to think our practices and concepts anew, philosophy must be willing to get its hands dirty: it must be willing to think substance and subject together, refusing to gainsay the intractable contradiction between the two. Philosophy is the act of thinking through this contradiction, not the fetish of its overcoming. [...]
3 notes · View notes
forensicated · 6 months
Text
Tumblr media Tumblr media Tumblr media Tumblr media Tumblr media Tumblr media
...and not forgetting Santa Dan's Super Special Little Helper!
Tony Twinkle Toes!
1 note · View note